Phenomenology, Applied Psychophysiology, and Behavioral Medicine
Donald Moss, Ph.D.
Prior to commencing training in applied psychophysiology and biofeedback,
this author had the benefit of studying phenomenological psychology and
philosophy for ten years, pursuing applications in psychology, psychiatry,
and education (Moss, 1978, 1981, 1984, 1989a, 1989b, 1992; Bollnow,
1966/1987; Straus, 1930/1982). Phenomenology and applied psychophysiology
may seem to present antagonistic viewpoints with no common ground. However,
in the first half of the twentieth century phenomenology offered to many
European researchers in psychiatry, medicine, and biology the same kind of
breakthrough that self-regulation theory later provided for American
researchers.
In European medicine and psychiatry, phenomenology provided a conceptual
breakthrough which allowed researchers to get beyond the narrow
reductionistic thinking of the time. Phenomenology also provided an
alternative methodological approach--still scientific yet less
restrictive--to a variety of problems, such as, the human experience of time
and space (Straus, 1966, 1963/1969; Minkowksi, 1933/1970); the
neurophysiology and psychology of body image (Plugge, 1970; Straus, 1967);
the disturbed reality perceptions and language of mentally ill persons (Binswanger,
1942; von Gebsattel, 1954); and the fragmented and disorganized thoughts and
actions of brain-damaged individuals (Merleau-Ponty, 1945/1962). The
Heidelberg internist von Weizsacker (1947a, 1947b) applied phenomenology to
illuminate problems in psychosomatic and internal medicine, and the Dutch
physiologist Buytendijk (1965/1974) used this perspective to develop a
phenomenological physiology of human motion and posture in the human
environment.
Phenomenology shares with applied psychophysiology an emphasis on the
unity of mind and body, a dissatisfaction with one-dimensional physicalistic
medicine, and an intolerance for mentalistic models which explain behavior
by hypothesized psychic mechanisms. Phenomenology placed its emphasis on a
philosophy of body-mind, or of the "body-subject," with an accent on how
close the expressive, human body is to personhood. Biofeedback in turn has
placed the emphasis on helping the human individual to enhance awareness and
control over the living body.
The present chapter will orient the reader to some of the most relevant
lessons of phenomenology for the fields of applied psychophysiology and
behavioral medicine: first, through an historical review of phenomenology;
second, through an examination of the phenomenological approach and
methodology; third, through a discussion of the clinical implications of
phenomenology; and fourth, through a review of parallels between the
phenomenology of consciousness and the neurofeedback movement.
Brief Review of Phenomenological Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology
Phenomenology, as a movement, began with the work of the Austrian
psychologist Franz Brentano who wrote a book titled Psychology from the
Empirical Standpoint (1874). Prior to Brentano psychologists such as Wundt
and Ebbinghaus attempted to explain the qualities of human thinking and
action via "associationism," by referring to the smallest elements of
experience, such as minute sensations and feelings, which come together in
association with one another to form higher mental complexes (Kockelmans,
1967, pp. 53-64). Brentano rejected this idea of breaking psychological
phenomena down into their most minute elements. He adopted an empirical
descriptive approach to psychology, to define and characterize the subject
matter of psychology (Kockelman, 1967, pp. 66-67). He identified
"intentionality" as the decisive characteristic of psychic phenomenonon,
which distinguished them from physical objects. Psychic acts are intentional
because they are oriented or directed toward some specific situation or
object beyond themselves, and can be meaningfully understood only by that
context. Later phenomenological researchers expanded this idea of
intentionality to emphasize the organism-environment relationship (Straus,
1969) and the unity of the human being with the world (Heidegger, 1927/1962;
Merleau-Ponty, 1945/1962).
The next significant figure in the development of phenomenology was
Edmund Husserl whose painstaking investigations of the field of
consciousness returned over and over to a fine-grained description of the
immediacy of human experiencing. Husserl developed the phenomenological
method as a way of objectively studying many phenomena that common sense
calls subjective: consciousness, the structure of time, and the emergence of
meaning (Husserl, 1900-1901/1970, 1925/1977). Husserl especially called for
the development of a phenomenological psychology which would set aside the
"naturalistic" modes of thinking used by medicine, biology, and physiology,
and remain with a specifically psychological perspective (Husserl,
1925/1977, P. 3; Kockelmans, 1967). He criticized those psychological
theories of his time which sought to explain a human experience by reference
to chemistry, physiology, or neurology, without exploring the immediate
purely psychological sense and organization of the experience (Giorgi,
1970).
Husserl also developed the concept of the "life world" -- the immediate
realm of everyday experiencing which we trust and take for granted before
and after our work days as scientists (1935-1937/1970). For Husserl, the
many scientific realities--the physical, atomic, and sub-atomic universe
studied by the physicist; the vital realm of
living processes studied by the biologist; or the realm of neuro-chemical
processes studied by the neuro-scientist -- are all secondary or derivative
realities, which receive their full meaning by reference back to this
immediate realm of waking and sleeping, living and dying, loving and
working. He does not devalue the scientific perspective but points out that
our scientific understanding of phenomena often proceeds by metaphor,
images, and linguistic constructions borrowed from everyday life. The
ultimate significance of scientific concepts is also dependent on their
impact on this life world. Joe Kamiya (1993), one of the founders of
biofeedback, has observed the same paradox: He emphasizes the contradiction
in the behavioral scientist who awakens in the morning, narrates his dreams
to his wife, discusses his feelings and opinions over breakfast, then
commutes to a laboratory where he excludes private experiences or
introspection as invalid or illusionary.
Phenomenological psychology understands the science of human behavior as
organized around various levels of analysis: Each successive level of
scientific analysis reflects a more microscopic or macroscopic view of the
same reality. The truth does not reside in any one level of analysis, yet
the everyday "life-world" of immediate human experiencing is the level which
gives meaning to the findings of all levels (Moss, 1981). A pathologist uses
anatomical knowledge to identify a lymphoma; this bare "fact" takes on
meaning as the human being faces the risk of death. A lack of availability
of serotonin in the synaptic cleft is a fact for biochemistry; its relevance
is found in the immediate sadness or despondency of the human being in
everyday life. The willful determination of that serotonin-lacking
individual to live fully and push toward greater athletic vigour in everyday
life may in turn impact back on the serotonin level in the unseen synaptic
cleft. The phenomenologist reminds us that the everyday "life world" is the
ultimate frame of reference for all scientific findings. At the end of the
working day the scientist leaves the laboratory and returns to the
macroscopic world of nature, landscapes, and beloved persons.
Later researchers within psychiatry, psychology, and the biological
sciences applied the concepts and approach of phenomenology to their
specific fields with rich results. Of special relevance for applied
psychophysiology are the French phenomenological philosopher Maurice
Merleau-Ponty, the German psychiatrist and neurologist Erwin Straus, and the
Swiss psychiatrist Medard Boss.
Merleau-Ponty shifted the focus of phenomenological research from the field
of consciousness and the structure of internal mental acts, to the structure
of behavior, viewed as intentionally directed toward a situation.
Merleau-Ponty defined the "mental" as the organization or structure of
behavior. In his principle works, The Structure of Behavior (1942/1963) and
the Phenomenology of Perception (1945/1962), Merleau-Ponty took the evidence
of the Gestalt psychologists, especially Kurt Goldstein's investigations of
neurologically damaged individuals, to explore the organization of normal
human movement and the embodied organism's relationship to the environment.
For Merleau-Ponty, phenomenology was never merely introspection; one
knows the human being through his behavioral involvement in situation and
world. "It is through my relation to 'things' that I know myself; inner
perception follows afterward..." (1945/1962, p. 383). For the
phenomenologist no human behavior and no neuro-physiological process can
ultimately be understood apart from its situational context; identify the
correct context and even the most bizarre or pathological behavior is
meaningful.
Merleau-Ponty developed Husserl's idea of an active constitution of
meaning further, with an empirical emphasis. Husserl pointed out that the
human mind actively works on the environment, shaping it and endowing it
with meaning, while being shaped in turn by culture, language, and
situation. Merleau-Ponty emphasized that as a bodily organism the human
being is "condemned to meaning," driven to actively interrogate its
environment, questioning and shaping meaning at a pre-verbal perceptual
level. Further, organism and environment organize and "co-constitute" one
another. The lived body, according to Merleau-Ponty, inhabits the world as
the heart inhabits the organism; the body "breathes life" into the world,
sustains it, and "with it forms a system" (1945/1962, p. 203). The textures
of the earth as we experience it mirror the organization of the human
sensorium.
Similarly motion and perception stand in a reciprocal relation, each shaping
the other (Merleau-Ponty, 1945/1962, p. 101-103). McConnville (1978, p. 110)
showed that "the perceptually meaningful structures of the spatial world are
not something passively registered on the retina, but something actively
solicited by a body which moves through space and engages the world."
For example, the normally hungry human body organizes around itself a
world in which the pathways to obtaining nourishment have a particular
perceptual prominence, and in turn the repeated encounter with varieties of
tempting foods can transform a satiated individual into a state of
subjective, felt hunger. The eating disordered individual with an obsessive
preoccupation perceives food cues where others notice nothing, and at the
same time creates a behavioral environment with cupboards full of junk food.
In turn this environment serves as a cue or trigger for out of control binge
behavior (Moss, 1989a, 1992).
In summary, Merleau-Ponty utilized the philosophical concepts of
intentionality and constitution, along with the psychological data of the
Gestaltists, to express the principles that American psychology
conceptualizes as self-regulation and systemic dysregulation. What emerged
was an image of an active organism contributing to the structure of its
environment, anticipating the neuropsychological view of Pribram (1960):
The shift is from the notion that an organism is a relatively
passive protoplasmic mass whose responses
are controlled by the arrangement of environmental
stimuli to a conception of an organism that has considerable control over
what will constitute stimulation. (1960, p. 4)
Erwin Straus drew on many examples from the annals of neurological and
psychiatric pathology, such as the phantom limb, to understand normal human
embodiment and the relationship of the embodied human being to the sensory
world (Straus, 1935/1963). He highlighted the essential experience of the
body as my own and the disruption of this experience in illness, when
disease appears as a foreign power attacking and overpowering one (Straus,
1967, 1963/1969). For Straus, the possessive experience of one's own body
marks the transition from physiology to psychological experiencing. The
elevated EMG level and presence of trigger points in a particular muscle
group is a physiological datum; for the human individual, however, the
essential problem is that "my head hurts, I cannot relax, and I'm becoming
worried about what's wrong with me." The personal pronouns mark the
threshold of psychology and the person (Moss, 1981b,1982).
Medard Boss, a Swiss psychiatrist, entered a long apprenticeship with the
German existential and phenomenological philosopher, Martin Heidegger, and
organized regular seminars with Heidegger and Swiss physicians seeking to
apply the phenomenological perspective to rethink the foundations of both
medicine and psychology (Boss, 1971/1979). Boss defined health as the total
"haleness and wholeness" of the human being, which is characterized by an
openness and flexible responsiveness to the world. In turn he defined
unhealthiness in human existence as "nothing but the privation, blocking,
impairment or constriction of this original openness and freedom" (Boss,
1988). He investigated psychosomatic illness as a means of jamming or
blocking one's openness to the world and to specific threatening situations
(Boss, 1971/1979; Moss, 1978). His theory resembles that of Wilhelm Reich,
who emphasized that muscular tensions serve as an armour against a full
range of emotional experiencing. From this perspective, the reduction of a
chronically elevated muscular tension may be a path toward recovery for a
person with chronic pain, but only if the individual at the same time
accepts the renewed openness to a variety of experiences. When EMG guided
muscular retraining is successful, the individual does more than modify a
physiological fact; the rehabilitated individual also rehabilitates his or
her access to a new world of mobility, action, and possibilities.
The Phenomenological Approach: A Methodological Pathway for Theory and
Research Phenomenological psychology is more an approach to knowledge than
it is a specific set of skills, facts or concepts. Phenomenology begins
methodologically with a dedication to return to the data of immediate
experience. Husserl counseled a careful cultivation of a "phenomenological
reduction," meaning that one begins by suspending all common sense and
scientific assumptions (Ashworth, 1996). In the moment of experiencing,
Husserl insisted, "we are here all beginners." To perceive freshly, one must
give up the passionate need to draw conclusions--the attitude that one has
understood the answers before posing questions. Further, Maurice
Merleau-Ponty advises that one must seek to recover a sense of wonder in the
face of the world. The phenomenological reduction "slackens the intentional
threads which attach us to the world and thus brings them to our notice...."
(Merleau-Ponty, 1945/1962, p. xiii). This strategy reveals the same world
once again as "strange and paradoxical" (1945/1962, p. xiii).
The phenomenologist achieves a sense of philosophical wonder by his/her
attention to experience but also accomplishes scientific ends. A return to
immediate experience often serves as a corrective against overly hasty
scientific conclusions, by disclosing the assumptions which bias scientific
inquiry. Husserl showed that even in everyday life our immediate perceptions
of the world are shaped through a "garb of ideas" (Ideenkleid) which clothes
the world (Husserl, 1935-1937/1970). The philosopher of science Paul
Feyerabend asserted that: "Observational reports, experimental reports,
'factual' statements, either contain theoretical assumptions or assert them
by the manner in which they are used" (1978, p. 31). In other words, the
particular ideas one takes for granted, about science, physiology, and
behavior, shape the observations and conclusions one arrives at in research.
In 1930, the German psychiatrist and neurologist Erwin Straus used this
"phenomenological reduction" to critique the unrecognized assumptions of
Pavlov's reflex theory and Freud's psychoanalytic drive theory. Straus
accepted many of the observations of Pavlov's research and Freud's case
studies, but showed how scientific assumptions biased their conclusions and
conceptual models. In doing so, Straus arrived at an innovative cognitive
theory of post-traumatic experiencing four decades before the cognitive
psychology of Beck and Lazarus (Moss, 1992). According to this theory, the
individual world of experience is an articulated structure supported by the
pillars of general meanings assimilated by an individual. The traumatic
event and its impact on an individual's experiencing can be understood from
the specific prior organization of this individual's experience-world, and
from the sweeping transformations the traumatic event brings about in this
structure of general meanings.
Erwin Straus contributed another valuable methodological perspective for
research. Straus formulated and repeatedly interrogated data with what he
called the "anthropological question": How must normal human experiencing
and behavior be organized, if such pathological phenomena as this are to be
possible (Straus, 1930/1982)? He expressed this idea already in his
dissertation in neurology: "Only the man who carries in himself a virtual
image of the intact whole is able to correctly perceive a torso" (1926, p.
123).
Straus' anthropological perspective can be applied to the phenomena of
applied psychophysiology: If we are to recognize the significance of
abnormal wave forms in muscular physiology, we might better grasp how such
wave forms occur in normal muscle physiology, and their significance for
intact locomotion within the human world. This means that we must become
more familiar with physiological norms based on well-functioning persons,
but it also means more. If we are to grasp the significance of a reduced
Electrodermal Response or a decreased peripheral temperature, we may need to
understand the transformation in the individual's experience of self and
world at that moment. The altered physiology of the stress response is a
derivative of the threatened organism's cognitive, emotional and behavioral
response to an emergency situation, and physical relaxation through
biofeedback is a strategy which assists the person in modifying that entire
relationship with the threatening situation.
On the American scene, Amedeo Giorgi (1970, 1979) applied the European
phenomenological perspective to propose that psychology be re-conceptualized
as a "human science." He emphasized that in the European and especially the
German sciences there has long existed an accepted distinction between the
natural sciences (Naturwissenschaften) and the "sciences of the human mind
or spirit" (Geisteswissenschaften). The American science of psychology has
largely emphasized the methodologies and assumptions of the natural
sciences--especially explanation, quantitative measurement, and
experimentation. Giorgi proposed a new emphasis within a "human science
psychology" on understanding, qualitative research, and description. In
other words, he proposed a new field of psychology which would spend more
time investigating what shame or anxiety are, how these unique experiences
unfold for the person and the meaning they take on in the individual's
experiencing, and place less emphasis on seeking to causally explain such
phenomena by means of neural mechanisms, correlations with certain life
events, or early predisposing factors. Giorgi proposed a psychology which
would spend less time measuring or predicting an emotional experience, and
more time understanding such phenomena (1970). He asserted that this human
science approach is not unscientific, but rather seeks a methodology and
assumptions which are more appropriate to the subject matter of human
behavior and experience.
Giorgi (1979) cited the German scholar Wilhelm Dilthey (1894) as
proposing a similar view of psychology as a descriptively oriented human
science seeking qualitative understanding. Dilthey's famous motto was:
"Nature we explain, the life of the soul we understand." Erwin Straus
(1930/1982) criticized the typical behavior of many psychological
researchers who proceed partway through a psychological exploration of some
phenomenon, then suddenly disappear below the surface, like a "diving duck
on a lake," and reappear with some submarine explanation about a
neurophysiological mechanism, without ever completing the psychological
investigation.
Giorgi's response to such a critique was that description is a valued
goal within psychological research and should aim at a qualitative
understanding of the meaningful structures of human behavior and experience.
Giorgi recognized the validity of natural scientifically oriented efforts at
explaining behavior by identifying underlying neural or biological
mechanisms. However, he insisted that such investigations should not serve
as a substitute for understanding a psychological phenomenon on its own
level. For example, the locus coeruleus, a subcortical structure in the
lower brain stem, might very well play a significant role in sustaining the
intense emotional arousal among victims of post-traumatic stress disorder,
but psychology must also study the human experience of terror as it is
perceived by each person.
B. F. Skinner voiced a similar critique against accepting any reference
to the "conceptual nervous system" as a cheap substitute for a behavioral
analysis. Skinner's understanding of behavior was different from the
phenomenological concept, but Skinner recognized that levels of analysis or
investigation should not be confused. Skinner also agreed with phenomenology
in regarding "behavior in context" as a fundamental datum and in favoring
relational descriptions over a search for underlying mechanisms (Cf., Chiesa,
1992).
Further, Merleau-Ponty showed in several of his re-analyses of the
findings of Gestalt psychology, that causative effects at the mechanistic or
physiological level are often changed by events at the human level of
meaning and experience (Merleau-Ponty, 1942/1963). Merleau-Ponty utilized
the example of El Greco, the Spanish painter, who was astigmatic and painted
stunning canvases with a mystic quality, showing elongated human beings and
elongated architectural structures. Merleau-Ponty asserts that a simple
physiological explanation, that El Greco's astigmatism caused him to paint
elongated, mystic pictures, is inadequate and over-simplified. Rather, El
Greco's mechanistic visual disorder served his artistic vision: "... his
liberty consisted only in justifying this accident of nature by infusing it
with a metaphysical meaning" (1942/1963, p. 203).
We could also cite the more contemporary findings of
psychoneuroimmunology, which remind us that bio-chemical or neuro-physiological
mechanisms alone rarely give a full account of a human disease process.
Rather, we must have recourse to the behavior, perception, cognitions, and
affective experiencing of the person with the disease. To paraphrase the
Greek physician, Hippocrates, it is not so important to know what kind of
disease the person has, as to know what kind of person has the disease
(Davies, 1996). Impaired immune function can causally render an individual
vulnerable to cancer, yet the will to live, a sense of humor, cultivation of
relaxation and meditative practices, personal journalling, and a variety of
similar emotionally and spiritually therapeutic exercises can in turn alter
those same immune functions in measurable ways (Borysenko, 1987; Cousins,
1979; Simonton, Mathews-Simonton, & Creighton, 1980; Siegel, 1986;
Pennebaker, Kiecolt-Glaser, & Glaser, 1988; and Pennebaker, 1995). The human
world of experience, creative acts, and meaning is the ultimate framework
within which all physiological processes within a human being are ultimately
organized. This is the final environment toward which human bio-chemical and
neuro-physiologic processes are directed.
Finally, American phenomenologically oriented researchers in psychology,
philosophy, and the health sciences have developed a number of creative
methodologies to place a greater emphasis on empirical and systematic
gathering and analysis of data. Giorgi (1970, 1979, 1985) has been a major
influence on these qualitative methodologies. The review of these
methodologies goes beyond the scope of this chapter. The reader is referred
to Aanstoos (1984), Giorgi (1985), Karlsson (1993), and Leder (1992), as
well as to the Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, many issues of which
contain empirical, phenomenological studies, with references to current
methodological developments.
The Phenomenological Approach and Clinical Care
Thomas Moore, in his recent work, Care of the Soul, expressed the
clinical equivalent to the phenomenological attitude:
... observance means first of all listening and looking carefully
at what is revealed in the suffering. An intent to heal can get
in the way of the healing. By doing less more is accomplished.
(p. 10)
The core of the phenomenological challenge to the behavioral medicine
clinician is the invitation to enter into the world and story of the
patient. The individual seeking help is isolated within personal suffering
and troubles, and the essential guiding principle of the phenomenological
approach is to stand with the patient and bridge that isolation. If the
clinician is to succeed in entering the patient's concerns, then he or she
must not only conceptualize but also co-experience the patient's unique
situation (Moss, 1989b, p. 196).
From the phenomenological perspective, health and disease are not simple
physiological facts, rather each involves qualitative differences in the
individual's relationship to the physical environment, in personal
temporality and spatiality, in relationships to the family and social world,
and in the struggle for identity (Moss, 1992, p. 179). As the Dutch
phenomenological psychiatrist Van den Berg showed, the sick individual --
whether mentally or physically ill -- lives a different existence and
inhabits a perceptually and experientially different world (1966, 1972).
Illness and suffering turn a person back upon him- or herself. The world
seems less inviting, loses its appeal, while at the same time one senses
that life goes on for others without one. Understanding the patient's
objective medical condition, as measured through a complete blood count, an
MRI, and other measures, without empathy for the "world of the sickbed,"
leaves the behavioral medicine clinician only half prepared.
Recent phenomenological investigations have explored the personal
experiencing of individuals faced with a variety of conditions and
situations: autism (Zaner, 1981), bereavement in general and the death of a
child (Smith, 1975; Brice, 1991), obesity (Moss, 1984, 1992), back pain
(Murphy, 1978), schizophrenia (Davidson, 1992), multiple sclerosis (Toombs,
1992), AIDS (Murphy, 1992), and adjustment to retirement (Hornstein and
Wapner, 1984). Such phenomenological descriptive investigations are valuable
in opening up the alien world of the suffering person, who otherwise remains
isolated with his or her malady.
The clinician's task, prior to implementing any specific technical
intervention, and throughout the course of any treatment, is to join with
the patient in his or her specific, altered mode of being in the world. The
clinician need not become psychotic with the psychotic, or experience a loss
of continuity with the neurologically impaired person, yet must lend
imagination and intuition to perceiving those disjointed and overwhelming
realities with the suffering individual.
Aaron Beck has developed a diversity of cognitive therapeutic
interventions for depression and anxiety. However, he counsels us to begin
phenomenologically, by listening to the client's perception of reality. All
confrontation and technical intervention follow this initial moment of
experiencing with the patient (Beck, 1979).
Phenomenology, Consciousness, and the Neurofeedback Movement
The resurgence of research in EEG feedback brings applied psychophysiology
back into the realm of diverse states of consciousness. Neurofeedback
involves the task of learning new modes of attending or being present.
Phenomenology began as a philosophy of consciousness, and has a rich
tradition of research into what it means to be conscious, to be present, or
to attend differently. This section will review the phenomenology of
consciousness briefly, highlighting four concepts relevant for the
neurophysiology of consciousness and the clinical application of EEG
feedback.
First, for phenomenology consciousness is not inside the head, and is for
the most part not an internal experience. Rather, consciousness consists of
an attunement and an orienting process toward objects and situations in the
world. The individual is conscious of something, and this something is in
the majority of instances something beyond the physical bounds of one's own
body. Actual internal experiencing, the focusing on pain, physical
sensations, or on some internal fear or worry, is often a morbid phenomenon,
characteristic of a troubled person or a diseased or injured body.
The variety of states of consciousness involve variations in how one is
present to the current situation. Research on the EEG shows that the
dominant frequency of electrical activity in the cortex covaries with
changes in one's attunement or manner of being aware of the present
environment. When the dominant electrical activity on the EEG is in the 13
to 35 Herz range (Beta waves), we find a wakeful individual, actively
scanning his environment, focusing on specific objects or problems, and
consciously thinking or deliberating about his current task. As we shift
toward slower wave activity, in the 8 to 12 Herz range (Alpha activity), we
find the person conscious, but more receptive and less task or goal
directed. As the cortical activity slows further, in the 4 to 7 Herz range
(Theta), we find the person in a kind of reverie, with wandering attention,
loosely connected (hypnogogic) imagery, and drowsiness.
This initial phenomenological characterization of the states of
consciousness accompanying various cortical frequency ranges is
oversimplistic, because we are speaking as though fairly wide frequency
bands were the only relevant variable in describing cortical activity.
Neuropsychologically the situation is much more complex. One can perceive
qualitative differences in the wave form of various theta range electrical
waves; these and other differences within the same frequency band may have
experiential correlates and functional consequences. Tansey (1985; 1993)
reports that narrow 1 Herz frequency bands differ qualitatively in their
significance for neuropsychological functioning. Sheer (1988), Sams (1995),
and others believe that activity in several neural structures centered
around 40 Herz is optimal for focused learning and memory tasks. Further,
the right-left symmetry, the topographical distribution of electrical
activity, and the subcortical orgins of a specific pattern of excitation,
and the absolute and relative power of brain activity all have significance
which requires much more investigation (Sterman, in press; Abarbanel, 1995).
In the future the phenomenology of the experiential correlates of these
diverse EEG states may come to rival the intricacies of Hindu and Buddhist
descriptions of human consciousness (Rama, 1981; Pannikar, 1977).
Neurofeedback training involves training the individual in alternative
ways of being present to situations. The fundamental promise of
neurofeedback is that it appears to present a simple tool useful in training
subjects to shift one's state of consciousness, or mode of being present,
through the use of immediate EEG feedback about one's currently dominant
brain state. This promise of neurofeedback is gaining credibility in
applications such as the treatment of attention deficit disorder and
addictive disorders. The promise remains to be proven with a host of other
applications. Whether training the EEG is the most effective pathway to
change for a specific problem or disorder, remains an empirical and not a
phenomenological question. To date for instance, it appears to be more
clinically-effective to treat panic disorder by cognitive-behavioral
therapy, but new protocols may qualify this conclusion.
For the individual with attention deficit and hyperactivity disorder
neurofeedback means learning a more focused and organized mode of presence
toward a specific academic problem or work situation. This is an alteration
in a state of consciousness. Neurophysiologically this involves giving
feedback to prompt and to guide the individual toward the suppression of
slow wave, less organized cortical rhythms (theta range activity), and the
enhancement of faster wave, more organized rhythms (beta range activity).
For the anxious individual the training process is approximately reverse;
the individual EEG baseline profiles vary a great deal in anxiety, but
frequently involve excesses of upper range beta wave activity, and a
scarcity of alpha range slower wave activity. The training process involves
learning a less vigilant, less tightly focused mode of presence, and in an
experiential sense a more trusting, open, and receptive approach to
situations.
Older descriptions from the phenomenology of meditative and mystical
consciousness come to mind, as parallel to this neurotherapy for anxiety.
The German mystic Johannes Tauler, living in the 14th century, advised the
spiritual novice to seek Gelassenheit, a mental and spiritual attitude of
"letting go-ness" (Moss, 1980). Tauler counseled the Christian seeking a
mystical oneness with God to give up effortful focusing on tasks and ends,
to cease measuring himself or herself by performance or achievement. Tauler
encouraged the beginner to learn inner stillness and to overcome inward
restlessness and disorder. Then one could perform all of one's actions from
this serene center (Moss, 1980).
The German philosopher Heidegger discussed a similar philosophical and
spiritual process of opening oneself, for which he used the same German
term, Gelassenheit or letting-be-ness. He advocated the individual living in
today's disordered amd rootless technological world to cultivate this
philosophical style of thinking, which creates a a "clearing in being,"
allowing what exists to shine forth in its own manner. Heidegger emphasizes
that this change in one's approach transforms not only one's inner self, but
also one's relatedness to the world as experienced (Heidegger, 1954; von
Eckartsberg & Valle, 1981).
When neurofeedback guides the anxious individual to enhance alpha-theta
range slow cortical activity, we may be assisting the individual practically
toward a similar spiritual and emotional transformation. Eugene Peniston's
protocol for neurofeedback with alcoholic and addictive individuals combines
visualization exercizes with neurofeedback, and explicitly draws on a
similar kind of self-transformation (Peniston & Kukolski, 1989).
Second, when one's state of consciousness alters, the physiognomy or face
of the world is transformed. This principle has implications for a variety
of changes in consciousness. To wake up and become conscious, for example,
means in an everyday sense that one is aware once again of having a
surrounding world. Ethologists have observed that an animal's virtual
behavioral environment is organized around the animal's instinctual needs
and drives -- of hunger or thirst, for example. The human individual's state
of consciousness -- which includes moodedness, cognitive expectancies, and
motivational sets -- similarly affects the manner in which this surrounding
world will be organized and experienced in this moment.
This principle can be illustrated by examples from psychopathology. The
paranoid individual vigilantly and suspiciously scans the surrounding
environment, seeking threat and danger, especially signs that the hostile
ones are out there intending to do one harm. Such a person sees a car pass,
that might have gone by yesterday, and wonders what or who is behind it, and
what danger this might portend. Such an individual does not experience the
danger as within his or her own head. Rather, the paranoia-world as it is
immediately experienced presents a face full of potential threats and
hazards.
In turn the normal consciousness of an individual feeling secure in his or
her familiar neighborhood or home, is marked by an emphasis on the presence
of familiar and comforting objects, sounds, and atmospheres. The German poet
Goethe comments on the individual awakening in the night to find that "Earth
-- this night too thou art abiding" (Faust, Part II).
Third, the technical interventions of neurofeedback, because they involve
a potential modification in states of consciousness, touch on the deepest
existential dimensions of the human person. It is these existential
dimensions which phenomenological psychologists and philosophers have
explored for much of this century. The rich cameos to be found in
phenomenological investigation may spark understanding of changes reported
by patients in neurofeedback.
We will touch briefly on the example of the phenomenology of memories and
fantasies of childhood. Access to and understanding of childhood
experiencing is crucial for psychotherapy and many applications of
neurofeedback. Elizabeth Loftus (1994) has recently focused on the dubious
validity of repressed memories recovered in psychotherapy. This is a
critical question, in both clinical practice and legal proceedings. The
phenomenological approach, however, deepens the question beyond the simple
problem of factual accuracy. In his book The poetics of reverie, Gaston
Bachelard (1960/1969) carried out a phenomenological reflection on the
images of childhood available in poetry, to explore adult reveries of
childhood. Bachelard observes that when one turns in daydreaming to one's
own childhood, one discovers not one but several child faces coming to meet
one, each seemingly a distinct person:
We were several ... in our primitive life. Only through the
accounts of others have we come to know of our unity. On the
thread of our history as told by others, year by year, we end up
resembling ourselves. We gather all our beings around the unity of
our name. (Bachelard, 1960/1969, p. 99)
Donnenberg (1973, p. 84) cited the German novelist Arno Schmidt, who
similarly observed that, even beyond childhood, life is not originally
experienced as a unity:
The events of our life spring forth. On the string of
meaninglessness, of
omnipresent leisure, the pearl chain of tiny unities of inner and outer
experiences is threaded. From midnight to midnight is not one day at all,
but rather 1440 minutes (and of these, on the other hand, at the most 50
are of any significance!) ...
My Life?! is no continuum! ... [rather]: a tray of glistening snapshots.
Bachelard proposes that access to childhood through reverie and
reminiscence lends unity and depth to adult identity. He observes that
imagination and memory are so interwoven as we look back at childhood, that
we may more accurately say that we are remembering our fantasies, and
fantasizing our memories: "The imagination ceaselessly revives and
illustrates the memory" (1960/1969, p. 20). In adult life childhood remains
a dimension ever present; the childhood within us yields a "consciousness of
roots" and according to Bachelard comforts the entire tree of one's being
(1960/1969, p. 20).
In an earlier book The poetics of space (1958/1964), Bachelard explored
the memories and fantasies of childhood which emerge as one pictures one's
original childhood home. The house for Bachelard is an archetype of the self
and world of the child:
For our house is our corner of the world. As has often been said, it is
our first universe, a real cosmos in every sense of the word. (p. 4)
Of course, thanks to the house, a great many of our memories are
housed, and if the house is a bit elaborate, if it has a cellar and a
garrett, nooks and corridors, our memories have refuges that are all
the more clearly delineated. (p. 8)
Memories of childhood adhere to the significant places of childhood, the
grandmother's kitchen with the fragrance of fresh bread, the father's
workshop with its forbidding shelves of tools, or the living room where the
family Christmas tree stood and where one still hears echoes of the carols
sung by the family.
The childhood which the adult recovers is not merely an array of facts,
but a clustered series of those other distinct childhoods which the child
has dreamed, the childhoods he or she wished for, as well as those which
should have been. In this regard Bachelard (1960/1969, p. 112) cites the
poet Alexandre Arnoux:
Of childhood I have so many
That I would get lost counting them.
Bachelard also describes childhood as remaining virtually incomplete.
When some phrase or event turns an adult back in revery, the remembering
surpasses the bare facts and rounds out the story (1960/1969, p. 106).
Bachelard views this reminiscence and fictional completion of one's
childhood as endowing childhood with layers of meaning it did not originally
possess. Bachelard sees this recovery and completion of childhood as part of
the "integration of the self" described by Jung.
Many patients who undergo physical and sexual abuse or other traumatic
experiences in early life have little or no access to reveries of childhood,
or to the identity integration process described by Bachelard. Rather they
are pursued by the terror lurking in their memories, or haunted by an
absence of memory. The most extreme instance of this is the individual with
a post-traumatic dissociative disorder. Dissociative individuals are caught
up living in an extreme form of response stereotypy. The child, unable to
face the full brutality and betrayal of the original abuse, dissociates
mentally. His or her awareness simply "goes away," or the event is
experienced numbly and without feeling, or another self crystalizes in the
moment of the abuse and "takes over." This original protective response,
however, increases the likelihood of continued reliance on dissociative
strategies throughout life. The process of dissociation prevents the
individual each time from experiencing the same memory or the same type of
emotional experience, which is never de-sensitized or mastered. Each
near-encounter evokes the same self-protective sequence of behavioral and
cognitive escaping, without real learning.
A patient reported to me that each time our therapeutic discussion
approached the time of her second grade year, she experienced entering a
tunnel with dim light, and had a sense of dimly seeing the same events at
her grandmother's house. As she tried to see more clearly she felt a
shattering, like of breaking glass and felt herself fragmented along with
the image. These shattering moments released extreme pain, disconnected from
any specific memory, and overwhelming despair. She lost any desire to live,
despaired of ever escaping her painful emotions, and became more avoidant of
discussing her childhood.
Many therapists doing verbal, psychodynamic psychotherapy with
dissociative patients in past years have encountered many such moments, in
which the patient is re-traumatized over and over in a therapy without
outcome.
The neurophysiology of traumatic anxiety is relevant here (van der Kolk,
1987; Kolb, 1987), highlighting a variety of brain mechanisms and processes
which are activated in extreme post-traumatic and dissociative experiencing.
These neurophysiological mechanisms reinforce the hopeless vicious circle
experienced by post-traumatic patients. The locus coeruleus in the lower
brainstem may be chronically aroused, activating noradrenergic pathways to
the limbic system, the cerebral cortex, the cerebelum, and the hippocampus.
With repeated traumatization, these mechanisms escape inhibitory control,
and produces chronic emotional arousal. Zajonc ( 1984) proposes that there
are direct neuropsychological pathways linking the retina and other aspects
of the sensorium to these affective excitatory mechanisms, without cognitive
mediation. Experientially the individual becomes hypervigilant and
oversensitive to a variety of triggers in everyday life, and remains unable
to regain control of his or her emotions. For example, without warning and
without thought, a certain kind of light reflecting in her windshield
excites terror in a woman driving her auto, who then can neither calm or
control her panic.
Consequently purely cognitive therapies often fail to interrupt the
sequence from a momentary sensation or image to overwhelming physiologic
arousal and emotional terror. The practical lesson is clear: Additional
techniques such as neurofeedback, EMDR, and hypnotic strategies are
necessary to modify the patient's response. Such strategies raise the hope
of interrupting this vicious cycle,
which is both an experiential and neurophysiological impediment to recovery.
Carol Manchester (1994) has advocated the use of a modified Peniston
neurofeedback protocol for individuals with post-traumatic dissociative
identity disorders, such as multiple personality disorder. The cultivation
of a slower wave alpha-theta brain state appears to facilitate both a faster
and more controlled recovery and healing of dissociated realms of traumatic
memories and childhood experiences. She proposes that teaching the patient
to re-integrate traumatic memories while in this state of low
neurophysiological arousal arousal minimizes the risk of re-traumatization.
For the clinician this novel approach is exciting, because individuals with
dissociative syndromes are treatment challenges. From the phenomenological
point of view it appears that both Manchester and Peniston are using
neurofeedback to train the patient to enter a receptive state of mind more
conducive to reverie and personality integration.
Fourth, phenomenological psychology insists that brain functions,
consciousness, and overt behavior stand in a circular, interactive
relationship. The current bias within biological psychology and psychiatry
tends to view the biochemistry of neural function as causing variations in
consciousness and behavior. However, current neuroscience research shows a
much more compex and reciprocal relationship between brain and behavior.
For example, recent research using PET imaging on the neural function of
individuals with severe obsessive compulsive disorder shows abnormally high
glucose metabolism in the caudate nucleus as well as in the the fronto-orbital
cortex and cingulate gyrus (Baxter, 1990). Pharmacological treatment with a
selective seritonin reuptake inhibitor (SSRI) such as Fluoxetine tends to
normalize the glucose metabolism in these neural centers. The decrease in
OCD symptoms, as measured by the Yale-Brown Obsessive Compulsive Scale (Y-BOCS),
correlates with the percent decrease in metabolic activity in the caudate
nucleus. However, behavioral therapy including repeated
exposure to anxiety-triggering situations also normalizes the glucose
metabolism in the same neural areas (Baxter, Schwartz, Bergman, Szuba, et
al, 1992). Behavior changes here produce neurophysiological changes.
Further, an earlier study by Isaac Marks and colleagues suggested that
the therepeutic effects were significantly lower when patients with OCD took
a seritonin stimulating medication (in this case Clomipramine), but were
instructed to avoid anxiety-provoking situations (Marks, Lelliott, Basoglu,
Noshirvani, Monteiro, Cohen, & Kasvikis, 1988). The behavioral exposure
appeared to facilitate the pharmacologically triggered changes.
The close linkages among neuro-chemistry, neural function, physiology,
cognition, and behavior are circular. Intervention at any level may effect
or potentiate significant change at all other levels. This "bio-neuro-physio-cognitive-behavioral
model" represents an extension of Elmer Green's "psychophysiological
principle, which states that: "...every change in the physiological state is
accompanied by an appropriate change in the mental emotional state,
conscious or unconscious, and conversely, every change in the mental
emotional state is accompanied by an appropriate change in the physiological
state" (Green, Green, & Walters, 1970). The challenge to behavioral medicine
is to identify and verify specific interventions which make use of this
principle with health impacting, clinically effective and cost-effective
results.
Conclusion: A Creative Partnership for Phenomenology and Applied
Pychophysiology
The technique of biofeedback was named only 25 years ago, at the first
conference in Santa Monica in 1969 of the Biofeedback Research Society, now
known as the Association for Applied Psychophysiology and Biofeedback.
Present in the creation of biofeedback were researchers whose primary
interest were in the study of private internal experiencing (Kamiya, 1976),
the psychology of consciousness (Ornstein, 1972), altered states of
consciousness and meditation (Tart, 1975), Eastern religion, and the
expansion of human potential and human awareness (Kamiya, 1993; Green &
Green, 1977). A recent letter appearing in the Biofeedback newsmagazine, and
signed by several leading figures in the Association for Applied
Psychophysiology and Biofeedback called for a re-affirmation of the original
values of the organization and a return to the original emphasis on
"consciousness, self-awareness, spirit, and self-regulation" (Kall, 1993).
Phenomenology evolved into a school of psychiatry and psychology studying
the human being involved in an active and self-actualizing dialogue with the
physical and cultural environment. This philosophical image of the human
being converges with the psycho-physiological theory of a self-regulating
biopsychosocial human organism in a systemic relationship with its
environment. The intent of this chapter is to encourage a new partnership,
in which the phenomenological approach and the rich findings of
phenomenological investigations may contribute to the theoretical and
empirical progress of applied psychophysiology and mind-body medicine.
REFERENCES
Because of the historical emphasis of this chapter, translated works are
listed whenever possible with their original date of publication, followed
by their English publication date (for example, Boss, 1971/1979).
Aanstoos, C. (Ed.). (1984). Exploring the lived world: Readings in
phenomenological psychology. West Georgia College Studies in the Social
Sciences, 23, 1-150.
Abarnel, A. (1995). Gates, states, rhythms, and resonances: The scientific
basis of neurofeedback training. Journal of Neurotherapy, 1 (2), 15-38.
Ashworth, P. (1996). Presuppose nothing! The suspension of assumptions in
phenomenological psychological methodology. Journal of Phenomenological
Psychology, 27 (1), 1-25.
Bachelard, G. (1960/1969). The poetics of reverie (trans. by D. Russell).
Boston: Beacon Press.
Bachelard, G. (1958/1964). The poetics of space (trans. by M. Jolas). NY:
Orion Press.
Baxter, L. R. (1990). Brain imaging as a tool in establishing a theory of
brain pathology in obsessive compulsive disorder. Journal of Clinical
Psychiatry, 51 (Suppl.), 22-25.
Baxter, L. R.; Schwartz, J. M.; Bergman, K. S.; Szuba, M. P.; Guze, B. H.;
Mazziotta, J. C. et al. (1992). Caudate glucose metabolic rate change with
both drug and behavior therapy for OCD. Archives of General Psychiatry, 49,
681-689.
Beck, A. T., Rush, A. J., Shaw, B. F., & Emery, G. (1979). Cognitive therapy
of depression. New York: Guilford Press.
Binswanger, L. (1942). Grundformen und Erkenntnis menschlichen Daseins.
(Basic forms and knowledge of human existence). Zurich: Niehans Verlag.
Bollnow, O. F. (1966/1987). Crisis and new beginning: Contributions to a
pedagogical anthropology. (D. Moss, Trans.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University
Press.
Borysenko, J. (1987). Minding the body, mending the mind. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley Publishing.
Boss, M. (1971/1979). Existential foundations of medicine and psychology.
N.Y.: Jason Aronson.
Boss, M. (1988). Recent considerations in Daseinsanalysis. In E. Craig
(Ed.), Psychotherapy for freedom: The daseinsanalytic way in psychology and
psychoanalysis. (Special edition). The Humanistic Psychologist, 16 (1),
58-74.
Brentano (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. (Psychology from
the empirical standpoint). Leipzig: Duncker Und Humboldt.
Brice, C. W. (1991). What forever means: An empirical-phenomenological
investigation of maternal mourning. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology,
22 (1), 16-38.
Buytendijk, F. J. J. (1965/1974). Prolegama to an anthropological
physiology. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Chiesa, M. (1992). Radical behaviorism and scientific frameworks: From
mechanistic to relational accounts. American Psychologist, 47 (11),
1287-1299.
Cousins, N. (1979). Anatomy of an illness as perceived by a patient. NY:
Norton.
Davidson, L. (1992). Developing an empirical-phenomenological approach to
schizophrenia research. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 23 (1),
3-15.
Davies, T. (1996, August). Mental health in the 21st century: The challenge
for primary care. In I. Wickramasekera (Chair), Mind-body medicine.
Symposium at the annual convention of the American Psychological
Association, Toronto.
Dilthey, W. (1894) Ideen uber eine beschreibende und zergliedernde
Psychologie (Ideas concerning a descriptive and analytic psychology).
Reprinted in W. Dilthey (1924), Gesammelten Schriften, IV. Leipzig and
Berlin.
Donnenberg, J. (1973). Bevorzugte Gattungen I: Kurzgeschichte, Reportage,
Protokoll. In W. Weiss, J. Donnenberg, A. Haslinger, & K. Rossbacher,
Gegenwartsliteratur (pp. 78-93). Stuttgart/Berlin/Koln/Mainz: Verlag W.
Kohlhammer.
Feyerabend, P. (1978). Against method. London: Verso Press.
Giorgi, A. (1970). Psychology as a human science. NY: Harper and Row.
Giorgi, A. (1979). Phenomenology and psychological theory. In A. Giorgi, R.
Knowles, and D. L. Smith (Eds.), Duquesne studies in phenomenological
psychology, vol. III. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Giorgi, A. (Ed.). (1985). Phenomenology and psychological research.
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Green, E., & Green, A. (1977). Beyond biofeedback. San Francisco: Delacorte
Press.
Green, E. E.; Green, A. M.; & Walters, E. D. (1970). Voluntary control of
internal states: Psychological and physiological. Journal of Transpersonal
Psychology, 2, 1-26.
Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and time. N.Y. Harper & Row.
Heidegger, M. (1954). Der Feldweg. Pfullingen: Gunther Neske Verlag.
Hornstein, G. A., & Wapner, S. (1984). The experience of the retiree's
social network during the transition to retirement. In Aanstoos, C. (Ed.),
Exploring the lived world: Readings in phenomenological psychology. West
Georgia College Studies in the Social Sciences, 23, 119-136.
Husserl, E. (1900-1901/1970). Logical investigations (2 vols.). (J. Findlay,
Trans.) New Jersey: Humanities Press.
Husserl, E. (1935-1937/1970). The crisis of European sciences and
transcendental phenomenology. (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern
University Press.
Husserl, E. (1925/1977). Phenomenological psychology. (J. Scanlon, Trans).
The Hague: Martinus Nijhof.
Kall, B. (1993). Biofeedback needs a change of heart; A hopeful beginning of
a dialogue. Biofeedback, 21 (2), 7.
Kamiya, J. (1976). Autoregulation of the EEG Alpha rhythm: A program for the
study of consciousness. In Biofeedback and self-control: An Aldine annual on
the regulation of bodily processes and consciousness. Chicago: Aldine
Publishing Company.
Kamiya, J. (1993). Personal correspondence.
Karlsson, G. (1993). Psychological qualitative research from a
phenomenological perspective. Stockholm: Almquvist and Wiksell
International.
Kockelmans, J. J. (1967). Edmund Husserl's phenomenological psychology.
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Kolb, L. C. (1987). Neurophysiologic hypotheses explaining post traumatic
stress disorders, American Journal of Psychiatry, 144, 989-995.
Leder, D. (Ed.). (1992). The body in medical thought and practice. The
Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Loftus, E. M. (1994). The myth of repressed memory. NY: St. Martin's Press.
Manchester, C. (1994, March). Neurotherapy for dissociative disorders. In E.
D. Walters (Chair), Symposium: EEG neurotherapy: New clinical applications.
Presented at the annual meeting of the Association for Applied
Psychophysiology and Biofeedback. Atlanta, Georgia.
Marks, I. M.; Lelliott, P.; Basoglu, M.; Noshirvani, H.; Monteiro, W.;
Cohen, D.; & Kasvikis, Y. (1988). Clomipramine, self-exposure, and
therapist-aided expsoure for obsessive-compulsive rituals. British Journal
of Psychiatry, 152, 522-534.
McConnville, M. (1978). The phenomenological approach to perception. In R.
Valle and M. King (Eds), Existential phenomenological alternatives for
psychology. NY: Oxford.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1942/1963). The structure of behavior. Boston: Beacon
Press.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/1962). Phenomenology of perception. (C. Smith,
Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Minkowski, E. (1933/1970). Lived time. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern
University Press.
Moore, T. (1990). Care of the soul: A guide for cultivating depth and
sacredness in everyday life. N.Y. Harper Collins.
Moss, D. (1978). Medard Boss and Daseinsanalysis. In R. Valle and M. King (Eds),
Existential phenomenological alternatives for psychology. NY: Oxford.
Moss, D. (1980). Transformation of self and world in Johannes Tauler's
mysticism. Revision: A Journal of Knowledge and Consciousness. 3 (2), 18-26.
Revised version in R. Valle, and R. Von Eckartsberg (Eds.), The metaphors of
consciousness (pp. 337-357). New York: Plenum,1981.
Moss, D. (1981a). Phenomenology and neuropsychology: Two approaches to
consciousness. In R. Valle & R. Von Eckartsberg (Eds.), Metaphors of
consciousness. N.Y.: Plenum.
Moss, D. (1981b). Erwin Straus and the problem of individuality. Human
Studies, 4 (1), 49-65.
Moss, D. (1982). Distortions in human embodiment: A study of surgically
treated obesity. In R. Bruzina and B. Wilshire (Eds.), Phenomenology:
Dialogues and bridges. Selected Studies in Phenomenology and Existential
Philosophy, vol. 8. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1982.
Moss, D. (1984). Corpulence and corporeality: Phenomenological perspectives
on the intestinal bypass patient. In Aanstoos, C. (Ed.), Exploring the lived
world: Readings in phenomenological psychology. West Georgia College Studies
in the Social Sciences, 23, 85-99.
Moss, D. (1989a). Brain, body, and world: Body image and the psychology of
the body. In R. S. Valle & S. Halling (Eds.), Existential-phenomenological
perspectives in psychology. NY: Plenum.
Moss, D. (1989b). Psychotherapy and human experience. In R. S. Valle & S.
Halling (Eds.), Existential-phenomenological perspectives in psychology. NY:
Plenum.
Moss, D. (1992). Obesity, objectification, and identity: The encounter with
the body as an object in obesity. In D. Leder (Ed.), The body in medical
thought and practice. The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Moss, D. (1992b). Cognitive therapy, phenomenology, and the struggle for
meaning. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology, 23 (1), 87-102.
Moss, D., & Keen, E. (1978, September). The nature of consciousness: The
existential-phenomenological approach. In R. Valle (Chair), The nature of
consciousness. Symposium conducted at the meeting of the American
Psychological Association, Toronto. Revised version in R. Valle, and R. Von
Eckartsberg (Eds.), The metaphors of consciousness. New York: Plenum, 1981.
Murphy, J. (1992) The body with AIDS: A post-structuralist approach. In D.
Leder (Ed.), The body in medical thought and practice. The Netherlands:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Murphy, M. A. (1978). The living of low back injury: A psychological
phenomenological investigation. Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University,
Pittsburgh, PA (University Microfilms # 78-18, 564).
Ornstein, R. E. (1972). The psychology of consciousness. NY: Penguin Books.
Pannikar, R. (1977). Colligite fragmenta: For an integration of reality. In
F. Eigo (Ed.), From alienation to at-oneness. Villanova, PA: Villanova
University Press.
Pennebaker, J. W. (1995). Emotion, disclosure, and health. Washington, D.C.:
American Psychological Association.
Pennebaker, J. W.; Kiecolt-Glaser, J. K.; & Glaser, R. (1988). Disclosure of
emotions and immune function: Health implications for psychotherapy. Journal
of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 56, 239-245.
Penniston, E. G.; & Kukolski, P. J. (1989). Alpha-theta brainwave training
and beta-endorphin levels in alcoholics. Alcoholism: Clinical and
Experimental Research, 13, 271-279.
Plugge, H. (1970). Vom Spielraum des Leibes (Concerning the action space of
the living body). Salzburg: Otto Muller Verlag.
Pribram, K. (1960). A review of theory in physiological psychology. Annual
Review of Psychology, 11, 1-40.
Rama, S. (1981). Energy of consciousness in the human personality. In R.
Valle, & R. Von Eckartsberg (Eds.), The metaphors of consciousness, pp.
315-324. New York: Plenum.
Sams, M. W. (1995). Mathematically derived frequency correlates in cerebral
function: Theoretical and clinical implications for neurofeedback training.
Journal of Neurotherapy, 1 (2), 1-14.
Schmidt, A. (1953/1995). Aus dem Leben eines Fauns. Hamburg: Rowohlt Verlag.
[English translation/edition in J. E. Woods (Transl.), (1995), Scenes from
the life of a faun. In Nobodaddy's children (pp. 1-92). Normal, Illinois:
Dalkey Archive Press.]
Sheer, D. E. (1988). A working cognitive model of attention-to fit in the
brain and in the clinic. In D. E. Sheer & K. Pribram (Eds.), Attention:
Cognition, brain function, and clinical application. NY: Academic Press.
Siegel, B. S. (1986). Love, medicine, and miracles: Lessons learned about
self-healing from a surgeon's experience with exceptional patients. NY:
Harper & Row.
Simonton, O. C.; Mathews-Simonton, S.; & Creighton, M. (1980). Getting well
again. NY: Bantam.
Smith, C. (1975). Bereavement: The contribution of phenomenological and
existential analysis to a greater understanding of the problem. British
Journal of Social Work, 5: 75-92.
Sterman, B. (in press). Physiological origins and functional correlates of
EEG rhthmic activities: implications for self-regulation.
Straus, E. (1926). Das Problem der Individualitat. (The problem of
individuality). Die Biologie der Person: Ein Handbuch der allgemeinen und
speziellen Konstitutionslehre. Vol. 1. Berlin and Vienna: Urban und
Schwarzenberg.
Straus, E. (1930/1982). Event and experience. In D. Moss (Transl)., Man,
time, and world: Two contributions to anthropological psychology.
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.
Straus, E. (1935/1963). The primary world of the senses. NY: Free Press of
Glencoe.
Straus, E. (1966). Phenomenological psychology: Selected papers. NY: Bsic
Books.
Straus, E. (1967). Phantoms and phantasmata. Paper presented at the Fourth
Lexington Conference on Phenomenology, Pure and Applied. Lexington,
Kentucky.
Straus, E. (1963/1969). Psychiatry and philosophy. In M. Natanson (Ed.),
Psychiatry and philosophy. N.Y.: Springer Verlag.
Tansey, M. (1985). Brain wave signatures: An index reflective of the brain's
functional neuroanatomy: Further findings on the effect of EEG sensorimotor
rhythm biofeedback training on the neurological precursors of learning
disabilities. International Journal of Psychophysiology, 3, 85-95.
Tansey, M. (1993). Ten year stability of EEG biofeedback results for a
hyperactive boy who failed fourth grade perceptually impaired class.
Biofeedback and Self-Regulation, 18, 33.
Tart, C. T. (1975). States of consciousness. NY: Dutton.
Toombs, K. (1992). The body in multiple sclerosis: A patient's perspective.
In D. Leder (Ed.), The body in medical thought and practice. The
Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Valle, R. S.; & von Eckartsberg, R. (1981). Heideggerian thinking and the
Eastern mind. In R. S. Valle & R. von Eckartsberg (Eds.), The metaphors of
consciousness, pp. 287-311). N.Y.: Plenum
van den Berg, J. H. (1966). The psychology of the sick bed. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press.
van den Berg, J. H. (1972). A different existence. Pittsburgh: Duquesne
University Press.
van der Kolk, B. A. (1987). Psychological trauma. Washington, D.C.: American
Psychiatric Press.
von Gebsattel, V. E. (1954). Prolegama einer medizinischer Anthropologie. (Prolegama
to a medical anthropology) Berlin: Springer.
von Weizsacker, V. E. (1947a). Falle und Probleme. (Cases and problems).
Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enk Verlag.
von Weizsacker, V. E. (1947b). Klinische Vorstellungen. (Clinical lectures).
Stuttgart: Hippocrates Verlag Marquardt & Cie.
Zajonc, R. B. (1984). On the primacy of affect. American Psychologist, 39
(2), 117-123.
Zaner, R. M. (1981). The context of self: A phenomenological inquiry using
medicine as a clue. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press. |